|
Partisanship,
Race, and the Public Intellectual
by Gerald Early
|
"The
problem," wrote John Dewey in Freedom and Culture,
"is to know what kind of culture is so free in itself that
it conceives and begets political freedom as its accompaniment
and consequence." I take it that Dewey thought this act
of recognition was a problem for the intellectual, specifically,
in the instance of this essay, the American intellectual who
lives in a society that professes freedom as a value to be cherished
virtually above all others, except, arguably, equality. But
Dewey seemed to be stating this as a unique epistemological
problem in a democratic society: how does one know this type
of culture that so professes freedom as its consequence and
what does it mean to know it.
It might
be said that intellectuals in our society of whatever political
persuasion try to seize the idea of freedom as their own. That
is to say, whether liberal or conservative, in our American
understanding of those terms as a kind of simplistic catch-all
for our great political divide, the partisan intellectual always
argues that his or her side is the side of freedom: the conservative
argues that limiting government coercion is freedom and all
freedom is essentially defined by how much one is disentangled
from the compulsions of the state; and the liberal argues that
the democratic state, as a bulwark against oppression and injustice,
as an agent in the equalization of power, is a necessary agent
in producing and safeguarding freedom. Naturally, both the liberal
and the conservative are quite willing to limit the freedom
of the people they dislike; that is, both liberal and conservative
define, each in his or her own terms, what can be called "that
which is so intolerable that it cannot be tolerated in a free
society." (Intellectuals would refer to the intolerable
not as people at all but forces; to impersonalise makes it easier
to generate passion, even hatred. For the force becomes something
inhuman, something distinctly other, whether it is the poor
or the criminal or the agents of state power in the conservative's
mind, or the corporation or the criminal justice system or the
bureaucracy of finance in the liberal's mind.)
In fact,
it seems impossible for either to conceive of freedom as anything
but the enhancement of the status of freedom for some and the
diminishing of the status of freedom for others. This is what
the culture wars, as they were once called a few years back,
were all about. We cannot have a culture that is so free in
itself that it conceives and begets political freedom as its
accompaniment and consequence, as its natural outgrowth, as
it were, unless we know it as this kind of culture, so argued
both liberals and conservatives. And in various sorts of learned
discourses, both liberal and conservative intellectuals described,
through a number of guises, what that kind of culture was: whether
it was a culture that supported popular simplifications of Marx,
Freud, Evolution, or Existentialism or a culture that condemned
vulgarity and subjectivity.
We have,
in recent years, heard a great deal about public intellectuals,
more, I think, than we had heard, say, before World War II,
more perhaps than we need to know or than the subject may be
worth. The term "intellectual" is a late 19th century
expression, and it came into existence not only with the mass
production of books and newspapers but, more importantly, the
invention of mass education, mass transportation and mass communications,
the modern research university, the rampant professionalization
of charity, welfare, and philanthropy, the rise of science,
the mass reproduction of everything from music to automobiles
that have created a consumer society, all of which were either
in full swing or had their roots in late-19th century western
culture. The items on the list I enumerated have gone into shaping
how we experience freedom and how we learn about it, and have
made the public intellectual a presence of some considerable
vigor.
The sheer
proliferation of the objects, diversions, and possibilities
for, life in modern society made modern society, as Walter Lippmann
pointed out in The Phantom Public, "not visible
to anybody, nor intelligible continuously and as a whole."
Abundance blunted not only the meaning of experience but also
the pleasure to be found in abundance itself. So, it might be
said that the public intellectual's job is to make the society
visible and intelligible in some holistic or specialized way
to itself, to make abundance at least a pleasurable experience,
if not entirely coherent, so that people could be cognizant
of freedom (whether they are being told to celebrate the abundance
of freedom as symbolized by the abundance of things and choices
they have or whether they are being told that they are being
unfairly denied or cheated of freedom by nefarious agents, even
by abundance itself; whether they are being told that true freedom
is external authority or whether they are being that true freedom
is utter antinom ianism; whether they are being told that true
freedom is absolute equality or whether they are being told
that true freedom is natural inequality).
The problem
was epistemological for the intellectuals and the public: "to
know what kind of culture is so free as to have political freedom
as its natural consequence." Lippmann also wrote that "the
citizen gives but little of his time to public affairs, has
but a casual interest in facts, and but a poor appetite for
theory." It is the public intellectual's job to provide
the citizen with an opinion, a rational, empirical, or rhetorical
scheme, about the things, which he or she cannot possibly sit
down to try to become truly informed about, whether it is the
bible made easy or a biography of Mozart. The public intellectual,
in the spirit of selling, a defining pastime in America which,
as Jacques Barzun has suggested, has made everyone anxious about
being on the shelf, as it were, is not required to be truly
sincere, only convincing. Public intellectuals are not meant
to teach so much as to persuade.
There is
a good deal of anti-intellectualism in American society, a fair
amount of which is generated by intellectuals themselves, whose
worst enemies are other intellectuals, and who are capable of
knowingly saying the most irresponsible, venomous, distorted
stuff imaginable. This anti-intellectualism can compromise what
intellectuals wish to do but it does not prevent it and sometimes
is an aid to the public intellectual's appeal. Many of these
matters are discussed in Jacques Barzun's 1959 work, House
of Intellect, one of the best, most accessible books on
the role of public intellectuals in American society.
A good deal
of the most recent discussion about public intellectuals has
been specifically about the number of highly visible black intellectuals
that have appeared on the scene since, say, 1980. It is not
terribly difficult to explain the arrival of these people as
a significant presence:
First,
race has become a nearly obsessive topic in American culture
these days and there is a need for a cadre of people who can
discuss it in relatively sophisticated terms, or at least, with
more nuance than one might encounter in the average newspaper.
Now, in many instances, whites still do talk about race or race
relations, but, more and more, especially in the realm of dissecting
and understanding the black perspective, the black intellectual
is called upon to interpret matters for the white public, and,
interestingly and increasingly, for the black public as well,
although clearly not in the same way for both. Or put another
way-a black intellectual is bankable as a public figure inasmuch
as he or she can speak for one public while being able to speak
to the other. It is a sign of an important change in American
democracy that such a figure is necessary for the organs and
media of the culture to create a coherent image or message of
what the culture aspires to be out of the profligate chaos of
what it is. But it must be understood that American society
constantly reshapes itself by reshaping the idea of freedom,
thus, reshaping the idea of the culture that defines itself
as that from which political freedom is a consequence. Why race
has become such an obsessive topic in American culture is, too,
fairly easy to discern and I shall discuss that momentarily.
But to return
to the issue of the arrival of the black public intellectual:
the second reason for their appearance is that there does now
exist what can be called a black public, that is, a large configuration
of educated African Americans with sufficient time on their
hands to cultivate themselves as responsible and knowledgeable
citizens; a black public that needs to be informed about and
aligned with a set of advocacy positions. In this way, the black
public is not different from how Walter Lippmann described the
public generally. Black public opinion counts for something,
and the marshaling of it in support or opposition to something
in this country can cause a crisis. Public intellectuals help
marshal public opinion. The other important point that Lippmann
raised about the public in general is its investment in "a
regime of rule, contract, and custom." The black public
is just beginning in important ways to legitimate its own system
of rule, contract, and custom and to engage seriously as equal
citi zens the rule, contract, and custom of the larger society.
Black intellectuals
are meant to function in both interpretative realms of the black
public and the general public. The rise of professionalism among
black Americans necessitates the need for a class of professional
intellectuals who are meant to serve as partisans of their interests,
to articulate and make coherent a number of view points within
the black community, or if not a number of disparate view points,
to legitimate a certain set of orthodoxies about the nature
of black experience, the meaning of black values, and the direction
of black interests. In other words, a black public needs a set
of intellectuals to help shape, not a black culture, but a useable
version of American culture and American ideology for the purpose
of maintaining a viable black identity that can, with moral
integrity and political astuteness, support the idea of an American
culture and American ideology.
The third
reason for the emergence of black intellectuals is that blacks
have achieved a sufficient presence at certain important cultural
institutions that produce and support intellectuals such as
research universities, government and corporate agencies, and
the world of public and private philanthropy. There were, of
course, black intellectuals before, say, 1960, but there were
hardly any places to sustain them. The most important institution
in the black community, the black church, was not a good place
of sustenance for intellectuals, although it did maintain a
few. Nor were black colleges good places, none of which could
be considered research institutions on the order that we might
normally think of. Black colleges did their bit, under-financed
and over-burdened as they were, to sustain black intellectual
life but it was not their primary purpose to do that. Beyond
this, there was virtually nothing in American society to support
a black person who wanted to live a life of the mind, a life
of ideas , except perhaps the Communist Party where most black
intellectuals and thinkers cut their teeth in this country before
1970. But that is another story. With the destruction of Jim
Crow, and the advent of affirmative action, much has changed
in this regard in the nurturing of blacks who wish to live the
intellectual's life which requires nearly as much maintenance
as supporting the life of a high-level performance athlete.
Both the
presence of black intellectuals in these institutions and places
have made both blacks and whites uneasy or unsure about what
claims can be made about the change in character in the institution
as a result of permitting blacks to be there. This unsettle-ness
has given that small number of blacks with access to these institutions
and who operate within them both a sense of visibility and a
curious sort of isolation that intensifies a need for racial
solidarity and for representative-ness in two senses that legitimate
racial solidarity. First, blacks demand that more blacks be
permitted into these institutions to provide a genuine representation
of the group in the institutions. Second, the blacks within
the institution are expected to represent the politics and psychology
of the group as a way of ensuring their own sense of being genuine.
This, in turn, legitimates their demand for blacks in the institution.
All of this is their effort to create within the professional
culture of the institution the political freedom that is the
consequence of any free institution, as we Americans all assume.
In other words, blacks are trying to make the institution work
for them as Americans seeking a workable American culture and
ideology.
Now, why
has the topic of race become such an obsession in the United
States must be considered. First, it must be remembered that
race and especially racism have been topics that have absorbed
both the popular and intellectual mind in this country for the
last few hundred years. They have figured tragically in our
political ideology, ambivalently in our moral philosophy and
science, in our social mores, in our religion, and in our popular
cultural expressions. So, the current preoccupation must be
understood as a continuation of a long-standing fixation. What
is different about the race obsession now is the unquenchable
need to have blacks talk about themselves, almost to the exclusion
of their being able to talk publicly about anything else. The
roots of this, I think, can be traced to the Harlem Renaissance,
a period in American social history that occurred roughly between
1919 and 1930, when blacks became highly visible in both popular
and high-brow culture as both objects and participants. It was
at this time that African Americans, living the south in great
numbers, migrated north and became an urban people, a people
associated with industrialization and modern life, a people
capable of launching a mass political movement (Marcus Garvey's
Universal Negro Improvement Association in 1917), of serious
vocational organization (Rube Foster started the Negro Baseball
Leagues in 1920 in Chicago), of absorbing and using contemporary
political and social theories, particularly socialism and sociology,
for their own ends.
These developments
certainly made it important to other black people that blacks
assess themselves rigorously and relentlessly. But what made
this important to whites was black people's association with
something that was very modern, indeed-not psychology, but psychologizing,
the popular belief in the power of manipulating mental and emotional
moods and states of being. Blacks became associated with a new
aesthetic movement called jazz at a time-with the emergence
of both records and radio-when music was starting to occupy
an important place in the psychological make-up of average people
because music was becoming so pervasive and because it was identified
with powerful anti-intellectual impulses. Blacks, in other words,
were central in inventing a revolutionary music at a time when
music was beginning to occupy a centrally important place in
human consciousness. Second, blacks were associated with underground
urban culture at a time when urban culture was exploding as
a vital force in human consciousnes s because of Prohibition.
It was these two connections between blacks and the new modern
American consciousness that made black public intellectual possible.
The need
to pscyhologize about freedom or to see freedom more as a set
of psychological moods or experiences through an art form like
jazz and a geography like the modern city rather than through
something explicitly political, made the idea of black people
talking about their experience attractive, indeed, essential
to whites in order for them to have an understanding of their
culture as something so free that political freedom was its
consequence. (Oddly, black people, in the public American mind,
have been symbols of slavery and thus, seen as repressed beings
but this has always been a relatively minor view. In the 20th
century especially, blacks have become psychologizing symbols
of freedom-artistic freedom, sexual freedom, freedom of consciousness.)
I think one can clearly see the nature of the problem of the
black public intellectual; he or she was and is a product, actually,
as cross-over figures, of anti-intellectual forces and not permitted
the same range of interests as their white counterparts. In
part, this happened because whites, on the whole, were never
very interested in having blacks talk about white experience
or any other experience but their own) in any useful way except
as a self-conscious black person reacting to it.
Now, Jacques
Barzun, in the opening chapter of House of Intellect, listed
three enemies of intellect: art, science, and philanthropy.
The black public intellectual has his or her versions of these
same enemies. In the realm of art, black music stands as enemy
to intellect because, first, music, even more intensely than
any other art because it is neither verbal nor visual, evokes
strong anti-intellectual, mystical, or sensual impulses. It
has hampered black public intellectuals, who feel rightly estranged
from a white intellectual tradition and insufficiently bolstered
by their own, to make black music essentially an intellectual
paradigm or model for their own work. Black public intellectuals
have also been hampered by social science, even though the social
sciences have produced a number of important black intellectuals.
Ralph Ellison and Albert Murray, among others, have pointed
to the downside of social science in their criticism of it:
its tendency to a jargon of abstraction; its analysis of "cure,"
as social science divides the world into a system of "behaviors,"
either pathological or healthy; its wish to quantify human experience,
so that it might conform to and have the objective force of
physical science. As the black critics of social science have
said, all of this hampers the way black intellectuals can discuss
black experience, especially as social science analysis so dominates
the discourse of African American intellectual life.
Philanthropy
is inevitable as the black public intellectual must advocate,
reasonably so in the light of his or her experience, an absolute
equality. But whether this demand for absolute equality is presented
as a militant leftism that is depended on a "structural"
analysis of so-called political reality or on an appeal to the
guilt or benevolence of the powerful as a "humanist"
or "religious" analysis of so-called human nature,
these are merely the masks for a rhetoric of compensation, a
rhetoric of reform. Inasmuch as black public intellectuals are
aware that they speak for a so-called "deficient"
group, or a group in need of enabling or help, they inevitably
wear one of these two masks. Indeed, the black public intellectual
is usually quite deeply aware of speaking for a "deficient"
group; as he or she makes greater claims for the accomplishments
of the group, the more apparent is the self-consciousness of
speaking for a "deficient" group. These three-music,
social science, and philanthropy-as politica l mission or religious
duty have debilitated by the black public intellectual.
I shall
close here but I think my brief, admittedly sketchy analysis
does, in some measure, explain both the attitudes and the works
of two contrasting black public intellectuals-Ralph Ellison,
who while writing about black music, particularly jazz, tried
desperately to fit himself into a traditional American literary
scheme-Twain, Hemingway, Eliot, Faulkner, James, and the like--because
he so abhorred the implicit anti-intellectualism in the materials
and language available to him as a black public intellectual;
and Amiri Baraka, on the other hand, who elevated black music
to an intellectual level, to a level where it was virtually
the only authentic expression of black American life and placed
on it, as Ellison noted, a burden it could not bear because
he found it impossible to fit himself in either a black or white
American literary scheme, and who, ultimately, devoted his energies
to a celebration and mythologizing of the anti-intellectualism
of the black public intellectual, an anti-intellectualism he
m asked as self-dramatizing political engagement. Each, in his
own way, devised his own vision of a culture so free in itself
that political freedom was its natural consequence: one, by
defending American democratic values that tended to box him
in politically as he more and more personified the "transcendent
artist" and the other by condemning them for a set of oppositional
values that had worth only because they were oppositional, a
tautology that traps many black intellectuals. I have only teased
apart a few very complex issues. There is a great deal more
to tell, in another place and at another time.

|
|
|